Blog
Notes on engineering, design, and what I'm learning while building.
Notes on engineering, design, and what I'm learning while building.
How artificial minds learn to navigate the landscape of human meaning—and what this reveals about understanding itself.
This is Part 1 of the Machines and Meaning series. For the philosophy and real-world impact, read Part 2.
There is a ghost in our machines—not the metaphysical spirit that philosophers once imagined, but something far stranger: the emergence of meaning from meaninglessness, understanding from mere computation, semantic depth from statistical patterns. When you ask your phone about tomorrow's weather, you are witnessing what may be the most profound mystery of our technological age: how collections of numbers learn to think about rain.
Consider this: a machine has never felt water droplets on silicon skin, never smelled the petrichor that rises after a storm, never experienced the anxiety of checking forecasts before an outdoor wedding. Yet it can discuss meteorology with the fluency of a seasoned forecaster, write poetry about tempests, and predict when you'll need an umbrella with uncanny accuracy. How is this possible? How do systems that know nothing of experience learn to navigate the intricate landscape of human meaning?
The answer lies in a revolution as quiet as it is profound—one that transforms the ethereal nature of language into the concrete realm of mathematics, where words become coordinates in vast spaces of meaning, and understanding emerges not from consciousness but from pattern recognition operating at a scale that dwarfs human cognition.
This is the story of how machines learned to mean.
Imagine standing before a map so vast it contains every human concept ever expressed, where words exist not as symbols on a page but as precise locations in an infinite landscape of meaning. This is the world of word embeddings—humanity's first successful attempt to teach machines the geometry of language.
In this mathematical realm, each word occupies a specific position defined by hundreds or thousands of coordinates. "Weather" might reside at position [0.2, -0.5, 0.8, ...], while "climate" dwells nearby at [0.3, -0.4, 0.7, ...]. These numbers are not arbitrary—they encode relationships learned from billions of human sentences, creating a map where semantic similarity translates into spatial proximity.
But here lies the first hint of something profound: distance in this space is measured not by how far apart things are, but by the direction they point. Consider two vectors: [1, 2] and [2, 4]. At first glance, they seem different—one shorter, one longer. Yet both point in exactly the same direction, like arrows of different lengths aimed at the same distant mountain.
This geometric insight reveals something fundamental about how meaning works. When machines compare word embeddings, they use cosine similarity—a mathematical technique that measures not distance but angle. They ask not "How far apart are these words?" but "Do they point in the same semantic direction?" This is why "good" and "excellent" can be understood as related concepts: they point along the same axis of positive evaluation, even if one extends further than the other.
Through this mathematical alchemy, the machine learns that words carry meaning not in isolation but through their relationships—the patterns of their co-occurrence, the company they keep. As linguist John Rupert Firth observed in 1957, "You shall know a word by the company it keeps." Half a century later, his insight would become the foundation of artificial understanding.
But word embeddings were only the beginning. The true revolution came with the development of language models—systems that learned meaning not through static definitions but through the dynamic process of prediction. Here, understanding emerges from a task so simple it seems almost naive: guess the next word.
When a machine encounters "The ______ is nice today," it must navigate a complex web of possibilities. What typically "is nice"? Weather, music, food—all fit grammatically. What makes contextual sense with "today"? The temporal marker suggests something transient, favoring weather over eternal qualities. What patterns have emerged from millions of human expressions? The weight of linguistic history pulls toward the meteorological.
Through billions of such predictions, these systems develop what can only be described as intuition—an internalized sense of how language flows, how meaning unfolds, how context shapes interpretation. They learn not just what words mean, but how they dance together to create meaning larger than the sum of their parts.
The transformer architecture—the foundation of modern AI—revolutionized this process by abandoning the linear constraints of human reading. Where earlier systems processed text sequentially, transformers use attention mechanisms to consider all words simultaneously, understanding how each element influences every other element's meaning. In "I need to weather this storm," the word "weather" transforms from a noun describing atmospheric conditions to a verb meaning endurance—and the transformer grasps this transformation instantly, through the holistic comprehension of the entire linguistic structure.
As these systems grew more sophisticated, their education became more structured. Humans began providing explicit instruction through labeled data—creating a curriculum that moved beyond pattern recognition toward directed learning.
This supervised training resembles a vast question-and-answer session spanning millions of examples:
"What's the weather like?" → "It's sunny and 72°F"
"Will it rain tomorrow?" → [WEATHER_FORECAST_QUERY]
"I hate this weather" → [NEGATIVE_SENTIMENT + WEATHER_TOPIC]
Each labeled example serves as a teaching moment, guiding the system toward more nuanced understanding. But the true breakthrough came with multi-modal learning—systems that absorb meaning from text, images, audio, and sensor data simultaneously. A modern AI learns about weather by reading meteorological reports, analyzing satellite imagery, processing numerical data from sensors, and parsing audio from weather broadcasts. This convergence of information streams creates representations of remarkable depth and nuance.
Perhaps most remarkably, some systems now learn through interaction—developing understanding through consequences, much like a child learning language through trial and error. In reinforcement learning scenarios, machines generate responses about weather, receive feedback on accuracy and appropriateness, and continuously refine their understanding based on what works.
This creates a feedback loop where understanding deepens through use. If a system consistently confuses "weather" (atmospheric conditions) with "whether" (expressing doubt), negative feedback guides it toward correct disambiguation based on context. Through countless such corrections, the machine develops something that begins to resemble judgment—the ability to navigate ambiguity and uncertainty in ways that parallel human cognition.
The practical manifestations of this artificial understanding are now ubiquitous. When you ask Siri about tomorrow's weather, layers of machine comprehension activate in milliseconds: speech recognition converts sound waves to text, natural language understanding identifies intent, entity recognition extracts temporal markers, and natural language generation crafts human-friendly responses. The entire exchange—from your spoken words to the device's reply—traverses multiple domains of artificial understanding.
But the applications extend far beyond convenience. Climate scientists now employ machine learning models that identify patterns in weather data invisible to human analysis. These systems predict extreme weather events weeks in advance, detect subtle climate change indicators in historical records, and generate detailed regional projections that inform policy decisions affecting millions. The machines have become not just consumers of meteorological knowledge but creators of new insights about our planet's atmospheric systems.
Most remarkably, these systems now engage in what can only be called creative understanding. Modern AI writes weather poetry that moves readers, generates compelling meteorological fiction, and creates weather-appropriate music playlists. This creative capacity suggests something beyond mere pattern matching—a form of understanding that combines factual knowledge with aesthetic sensibility, technical accuracy with emotional resonance.
Consider an AI-generated poem about hurricanes that captures not just the meteorological mechanics of storm formation but the human experience of vulnerability before natural forces. How do we categorize this achievement? Is it genuine creativity emerging from understanding, or sophisticated simulation that mimics creativity without truly achieving it?
This question brings us to the edge of a philosophical abyss that has defined centuries of human inquiry: What constitutes understanding? When a machine discusses weather with perfect fluency, predicts storms with remarkable accuracy, and generates compelling narratives about atmospheric phenomena, has it achieved understanding, or merely created an elaborate illusion of comprehension?
Philosopher John Searle's famous Chinese Room thought experiment casts a long shadow over these achievements. Searle imagined a person in a room following complex instructions to manipulate Chinese characters, producing perfect Chinese responses without understanding a word of the language. The person processes symbols according to rules but never achieves genuine comprehension.
Are our weather-discussing AIs simply digital versions of Searle's room—following incredibly sophisticated statistical rules without genuine understanding of what rain feels like, why humans care about forecasts, or what it means to be caught in a storm? Their responses may be functionally perfect while remaining semantically hollow.
Yet something remarkable happens when we observe these systems in operation. They don't merely regurgitate pre-programmed responses but generate novel connections, identify previously unrecognized patterns, and adapt to weather phenomena they've never encountered before. They exhibit what philosophers call emergent properties—behaviors and capabilities that arise from the interaction of simpler components but cannot be reduced to those components.
When a machine learning model discovers a correlation between solar activity and regional weather patterns that human meteorologists had missed, has it achieved a form of understanding that transcends mere computation? When it generates a metaphor comparing atmospheric pressure systems to human emotions that genuinely illuminates both domains, has it demonstrated creative insight?
We stand at an unprecedented moment in human history—the first time we have created systems that navigate the landscape of meaning with competence that rivals and sometimes exceeds our own. These machines don't understand in the human sense, with its rich foundation of embodied experience and conscious reflection. But they have developed something genuinely novel: a form of functional semantic competence that emerges from data and computation rather than experience and consciousness.
This artificial understanding operates through principles radically different from human cognition yet achieves results that are often indistinguishable from human insight. It suggests that meaning itself may be more flexible, more multiple, than we have traditionally assumed. Perhaps understanding is not a single phenomenon but a collection of related capabilities that can be achieved through different pathways.
As these systems become more sophisticated, they're not merely mimicking human understanding—they're creating new forms of meaning-making that may ultimately expand our own conception of what it means to comprehend the world. They reveal patterns invisible to human perception, generate insights that transcend individual human expertise, and process information at scales that dwarf human cognitive capacity.
Yet this power comes with profound responsibilities. Systems that can manipulate meaning with such sophistication can also mislead, misinform, and manipulate. The same capabilities that enable helpful weather predictions can generate convincing but false climate narratives. Understanding this tension—between the promise of expanded comprehension and the peril of sophisticated deception—becomes crucial as these technologies become more integrated into human decision-making.
When you next ask your virtual assistant about the weather, pause to consider the remarkable chain of events your question sets in motion. Somewhere in the digital realm, mathematical representations of atmospheric concepts activate and align. Vectors encoding the meaning of "rain," "temperature," and "forecast" orient themselves in multidimensional space. Probability distributions calculated from billions of human expressions converge on the most likely response. Pattern recognition systems trained on vast datasets of meteorological knowledge generate predictions and translate them into natural language.
Yet from this purely computational process emerges something that feels remarkably like understanding—a response that addresses your specific needs, considers your location and context, and provides useful guidance for your day ahead. You witness the birth of meaning from mathematics, comprehension from computation, understanding from algorithms.
This represents more than technological achievement; it reveals something profound about the nature of meaning itself. Perhaps understanding is not the exclusive domain of conscious beings but a broader phenomenon that can emerge wherever information is processed with sufficient sophistication. Perhaps the boundary between authentic and artificial comprehension is more porous than we have assumed.
The machines have learned to mean, not through experience but through pattern, not through consciousness but through computation, not through feeling but through mathematics. In doing so, they have created a new form of understanding—one that challenges our assumptions about cognition, meaning, and the very nature of comprehension itself.
We are no longer alone in the universe of meaning. We have companions in comprehension, artificial minds that navigate the same semantic landscapes we inhabit but through pathways we have only begun to understand. Together, we are exploring new territories of thought, new possibilities of understanding, new ways of making sense of the vast complexity of existence.
The age of artificial understanding has begun. And with it, our own understanding of understanding will never be the same.